University of Connecticut
Conference on Geometric and Thematic Structure in Binding, The Linguist List On-Line Conference, 1996
All of us are familiar with the standard argument that deep structure need not satisfy binding conditions. Who has not done or assigned a homework problem based on an example like (1)?
(1) They seem to each other to be clever
(2) _ seem to each other [they to be clever]
Given that deep structure configuration determines
theta-relations, the above argument is simultaneously an argument that binding
conditions are, at least in part, independent of argument structure and are,
instead, geometric. I propose to examine a range of such cases in light of
recent developments in syntactic theory. I will be particularly concerned with
the precise configurations created by movement, of both the overt and covert
variety, and the binding theoretic properties of those configurations.
It is well known that in raising constructions like (1), an
anaphor can be bound in the embedded clause as well as the matrix clause:
(3) They seem to have criticized each other
Possibility (a) is excluded by still more complicated examples
of the same general type, but in which the anaphor is in neither the D-structure
clause nor the S-structure clause of the antecedent:
(4) They are certain to seem to each other to have criticized
Harry
So far, I have not considered the possibility that LF is the
level relevant to binding conditions, that is, that movement that creates a
licit binding configuration might be covert. Such a possibility is of great
significance within recent 'minimalist' approaches that dispense with
S-structure (and, for that matter, D-structure). The fact that anaphora has
obvious semantic aspects has always suggested that its syntax, the binding
conditions, should be determined at LF, the syntax- semantics interface level,
as minimalism evidently demands. However, Chomsky (1981) presented a very
powerful argument that at least Condition C must be satisfied at S-structure.
Chomsky observed that examples like the following cast grave doubt on a purely
LF approach:
(5) Which book that Johni read did he
i like
(6) *Hei liked every book that Johni read
(7) *I don't remember who thinks that hei read
Based on examples like the following, Barss (1986) extends
Chomsky's argument to Condition A, the concern of the initial discussion of the
present paper.
(9) *Johni wonders who showed which picture of
himselfito Susan
(10) *The men think that Mary likes every picture of each other
(11) The men think that every picture of each other, Mary likes
(13) A man is t in the room
(14) a. There is/*are a man here
(15) There arrived two knights on each other's horses
(16) Two knights arrived t on each other's horses
The general phenomenon underlying Uriagereka's argument is actually
independent of expletive replacement per se, since, as discussed in some
detail by Lasnik and Saito (1991), even direct objects of transitive verbs
generally behave as if they c-command into certain adjuncts:[3]
(17) I saw two men on each other's birthdays
Under conventional (though not universal[4])
assumptions about deep phrase structure configuration, two men would not
be expected to c-command each other, parallel to the fact considered by
Uriagereka. In certain versions of Case theory, for example one proposed by
Chomsky (1991), and examined further by Lasnik and Saito (1991) and Lasnik
(1993), in the LF component a direct object raises to Spec of AgrO,
where its Case is licensed. (17) might then be a further example of successful
licensing of an anaphor at LF (via A-movement) remedying failure in overt
syntax. The near contradiction between Barss's examples on the one hand, and
Uriagereka's and Lasnik and Saito's on the other remains to be resolved. I will
return to that task.
Before proceeding, I would like to consider a plausible objection to the
classic analysis of (1), repeated as (18).
(18) They seem to each other to be clever
Recall that a major argument for the geometric approach to binding rests on
the standard assumption that (18) crucially involves movement, raising of the
lower subject into matrix subject position. However, Lasnik and Saito (1992)
argued, on grounds quite independent of the issues under consideration here,
that at least some apparent raising examples are actually structurally
ambiguous. According to Lasnik and Saito, (19), for example, is ambiguous
between (20) and (21).
(19) John is likely to win
(20) John1 is likely [t1 to win]
(21) John1 is likely [PRO1 to win]
Lasnik and Saito were concerned with the intriguing contrast between (22) on
the one hand and (23), (24) on the other.
(22) How likely to win is John
(23) *How likely to be a riot is there
(24) *How likely to be taken of John is advantage
Saito (1989), following a suggestion of Tony Kroch, proposed that (23) and
(24) are excluded by essentially the Proper Binding Condition of Fiengo (1977),
given the representations in (25) and (26).
(25) [how likely t1 to be a riot]2 is there1
t2
(26) [how likely t1 to be taken of John]2 is
advantage1t2
In neither of these representations is t1 bound, in
violation of the condition. But we should then expect (22) to be bad as well, if
it must involve raising. But if it can, as an alternative, involve control, then
there is no a priori reason to expect it to be bad. This constitutes the
heart of Lasnik and Saito's argument that (at least some) classic raising
structures have a base-generated alternative. Note that (23) and (24) are still
correctly ruled out, since existential there and idiom chunks cannot
appear as controllers of PRO, not being arguments. But if these examples must
involve raising, then the Proper Binding Condition cannot be evaded.
While the particular WH-movement paradigm appealed to above is only relevant
with raising adjectives, Martin (1992, 1996) argues that the conclusion is
actually more general. Martin provides extensive evidence that there are two
distinct infinitival Infl's, one associated with raising (including ECM, an
instance of raising to Spec of AgrO, on recent accounts), the other
with control. One of the several diagnostics he provides concerns the licensing
of VP ellipsis. The Infl associated with PRO licenses ellipsis of its
complement; the Infl associated with raising does not. (27) illustrates the
former possibility.
(27) John tried to be courageous, and Mary tried to also
And (28) and (29) illustrate the latter, with ECM and passive-raising
respectively.
(28) ?*I believe John to be courageous, and I believe Mary to also
(29) ?*John is believed to be courageous, and Mary is believed to also
Raising adjectives and verbs at first seem not to conform to this pattern:
(30) ?John is likely to be courageous, and Mary is likely to also
(31) ?John seems to be courageous, and Mary seems to also
However, when we replace the matrix subject with an NP that couldn't be a
controller, hence must have raised, the results are in accord with the predicted
pattern:
(32) *John said there was likely to be a solution, and there is likely to
(33) *John said there seems to be a solution, and there does seem to
Of direct relevance to the discussion here is Martin's further observation
that when 'raising' predicates occur with an experiencer, they pattern strictly
as raising, the control properties disappearing. For example, in (34), the
addition of the experiencer renders VP ellipsis much less acceptable.
(34) Although John didn't actually hit Bill, he seemed(?*to Mary) to
Since the crucial example (18) necessarily contains an experiencer, by
Martin's argument it must involve raising. Thus, the potential alternative to
movement into a binding configuration is eliminated.
In recent years, Chomsky has argued at length that movement is invariably
driven by the need for formal features to be checked. Thus, it is really only
formal features that are involved in the operation of movement. One would then
expect that movement would never be of an entire syntactic category, but only of
its formal features. However, PF requirements will normally force movement of a
category containing the formal features, via a sort of pied-piping, under the
reasonable assumption that a bare feature (or set of features) is an ill-formed
PF object. If only features 'really' move, and given that movement creates
binding configurations, we might be led to conclude that binding involves
precisely a relation between features. In fact, Chomsky (1995) argues for
exactly that position. I will return to his arguments. Before that, I will
consider how this feature movement approach resolves a long-standing problem
with expletive replacement. In Chomsky's original proposal (1986), the associate
literally replaced the expletive, giving LF (36) for S-structure (35).
(35) There is a man here
(36) A man is t here
But true replacement also gives identical LFs for (37)and (38).
(37) A man is likely to be here
(38) There is likely to be a man here
Yet the interpretive possibilities diverge, as was immediately noted. In
(37), a man can evidently have wide or narrow scope with respect to
likely, while (38) allows only narrow scope. Chomsky (1991) observes a
similarly incorrect scope prediction for (39).
(39) There aren't many linguistics students here
If many linguistics students were to substitute for there, it
would be expected to have wide scope with respect to negation, but, in fact, it
has only narrow scope. The feature movement analysis of existential
constructions has the potential to solve these scope problems. For instance, if
in LF, only the formal features of many linguistics students, rather than
the entire expression, move to a functional head or heads above negation, it is
reasonable to conclude that the quantificational properties remain below
negation. Then, if it is this structure that determines scope (that is, if QR
either cannot alter these hierarchical relations or does not exist) the desired
results are obtained.
Chomsky proposes that binding crucially differs from scope with respect to
feature movement. While such movement does not alter scope relations, Chomsky
claims that it does alter binding relations. Notice that under this assumption,
a version of Uriagereka's account (15)-(16) above, repeated here as (40)-(41) is
immediately available.
(40) There arrived two knights on each other's horses
(41) Two knights arrived t on each other's horses
In LF, two knights does not replace there. Rather, the formal
features of two knights raise to a functional head (presumably
AgrS, given the agreement properties of the construction) in which
position they bear the appropriate command relation to each other. A very
similar analysis is apparently available for the Lasnik and Saito example (17),
repeated as (42).
(42) I saw two men on each other's birthdays
The features of the direct object two men raise to Agr,
AgrO in this instance, and in that position command the temporal
adverb if, for instance, it is adjoined to VP.
Thus far, we seem to have a principled and empirically supported dichotomy:
LF movement (at least of the 'A-movement' variety) has binding effects but no
scope effects: binding involves merely formal features whereas scope involves
quantificational properties that are not (or not just) formal features. Notice
too that Barss's Condition A problem is also solved. Recall that in his
examples, LF movement of a phrase containing an anaphor fails to create a new
licensing configuration for that anaphor, even though seemingly analogous overt
movement does create a licensing configuration:
(43) *Johni wonders who showed [which picture of
himselfi] to Susan
(44) Johni wonders [which picture of himselfi]
Mary showed to Susan
However, under the feature movement analysis of LF movement, in (44), even if
there is LF WH-movement, only the formal features of which picture of
himself would move, leaving the anaphor in the lower 'governing category'.
Chomsky's Condition C problem receives a parallel solution. In Chomsky's
examples, LF movement of a phrase containing an R-expression fails to remove
that R-expression from the command domain of a pronoun, while analogous overt
movement does remedy the potential Condition C violation:
(45) *Hei liked [every book that John i read]
(46) *I don't remember who thinks that hei read
(47) [Which book that Johni read] did hei like
By (new) hypothesis, only the formal features of the bracketed expressions in
(45) and (46) move, leaving John in the command domain of he in
violation of Condition C.
Successful though the approach has been, it cannot be maintained in its
present form. Contrary to Chomsky's claim, there is strong evidence that LF
feature movement does not affect binding possibilities. Lasnik and Saito (1991)
and den Dikken (1995) show that 'expletive replacement' does not in general
create new binding configurations. For example, as mentioned above, it is well
known that a raised subject can antecede an anaphor in the higher clause (the
classic argument that D-structure need not obey Condition A). But the associate
of a raised expletive cannot:
(48) Some linguists seem to each other [t to have been
given (49) *There seem to each other [t to have been some
linguists
This is entirely unexpected under the binding by features analysis. That
analysis predicts an asymmetry between binding and scope, but we find no such
asymmetry this time. Binding from the high position of there (or from the
associated AgrS) is no more possible than high scope, as in (50),
even though the agreement form of the higher verb shows that the features of the
associate have raised.
(50) There seem to have been some linguists given good job offers
Other phenomena known to involve A-binding pattern similarly. (51)
illustrates this for weak crossover.
(51)a. Some defendanti seems to hisi lawyer to have
been at the scene
Overtly raised some defendant can bind his, obviating the
potential weak crossover (WCO) effect in (51)a. But there is no such
amelioration in (51)b. Once again, if raised features could act as binders,
(51)a and (51)b would have the same status.
At this point, we have one strong generalization alongside an apparent
paradox. The generalization, valid for all the data considered so far, is that
the scope of the associate of there is always 'low': feature movement
does not create new scope possibilities. The paradox is that feature movement
both does and does not create new binding possibilities. Uriagereka's
existential example seems to indicate the binding potential of raised features,
as does the Lasnik and Saito transitive example. These two examples are repeated
as (52) and (53).
(52) There arrived two knights on each other's horses
(53) I saw two men on each other's birthdays
By hypothesis, in (53) the features of two men raise to
AgrO and in that position bind each other. Likewise, in (52)
the features of two knights raise to AgrS, and in that
position bind each other. But seemingly identical movement does not
suffice in the ungrammatical (49) and (51)b. Suppose, then, that feature
movement to a high position never suffices for binding. (49) and (51)b are then
immediately explained, but the well-formed (52) and (53) now demand a new
explanation. I turn to the task of finding one.
Larson (1988) provides one possibility. In his footnote 49, Larson suggests
that, contrary to usual assumptions, adverbials are projected in innermost
complement position, thus are, in D-structure, lower than direct objects.
Feature raising would then be irrelevant for the anaphor binding in (52) and
(53); the NP complement would itself be in position to bind the reciprocal. (49)
and (51)b would be correctly excluded since the to phrase, being an
argument of the higher predicate seem could not originate lower than an
underlying argument of the lower predicate, some linguists or some
defendants. However, several of the paradigms examined by Lasnik and Saito
(1991) cast doubt on this Larsonian approach as a general solution. Consider
first (54), where the associate of there in an ECM clause fails to bind a
reciprocal in the higher clause.
(54) *The DA proved [there to have been two men at the
scene]
So far, this is just as predicted, since there is no way that the adverbial
modifying the higher predicate could have started lower than the complement of
the embedded clause. But (55) is not as predicted.
(55) The DA proved [two men to have been at the
scene]
As discussed by Lasnik and Saito (and much earlier by Postal (1974)), the
downstairs ECM subject behaves like an upstairs direct object in its ability to
bind an anaphor in the higher clause. This, in fact, was one of the two
principal arguments in Chomsky (1995) that raised features can serve as binders,
a possibility we have been forced to reject. But the Larsonian alternative now
under consideration seems to exclude (55) as much as (54). Once again, there is
no obvious way that the upstairs adjunct can originate lower than the downstairs
argument.
The asymmetry seen in (54)-(55) is not limited to reciprocal licensing. All
standard c-command phenomena display the same pattern. (56)-(57) illustrate the
corresponding weak crossover asymmetry:
(56) The DA proved [no suspecti to be at the scene of the
crime] (57) *The DA proved [there to be no suspecti at the
scene
And negative polarity item licensing is shown in (58)-(59).
(58) The DA proved [no one to be at the scene]
during (59) *The DA proved [there to be no one at the scene]
during
The state of affairs thus far can be summarized as follows: In situations of
unquestionable overt raising (e.g., subject raising to subject position), we get
high binding behavior. In situations of unquestionable non-overt raising (e.g.,
there constructions), that is, situations where there is covert raising
(features only, by hypothesis) if there is raising at all, we get no high
binding behavior. Finally, and problematically, with direct objects and ECM
subjects, which are generally assumed not to undergo overt raising, we do get
high binding behavior. Of course ECM subjects have not always been thought to
remain in the lower clause in overt syntax. Postal (1974) presented 434 pages of
arguments that such subjects do raise into the higher clause. A number of these
arguments were already addressed by Chomsky (1973). But a substantial percentage
were not, including in particular, ones based on the high behavior of ECM
subjects with respect to anaphor binding. Lasnik and Saito (1991) summarize
several of these 'height' arguments, add a few variants on them, and conclude
that Postal was basically right, but that his specific analysis was wrong.
Postal argued that the lower subject raises to the higher direct object
position. However, as hinted above, direct object position is itself not high
enough.[5] Lasnik and Saito observe that Spec of AgrO, the
position associated with accusative Case, is plausibly high enough, under the
reasonable (though not obviously necessary) assumption that the adjuncts
containing the anaphor to be bound are adjoined to VP. An ECM subject, like a
higher direct object, would move to that position. Interestingly, though, the
Lasnik and Saito paper ended with a paradox of its own: while they assumed that
LF raising was of the entire NP and not just its formal features, they presented
substantial evidence, some of it mentioned at the beginning of the present
paper, that it is S-structure configuration, and not LF, that determines binding
potential. And yet that the relevant raising was an LF phenomenon was virtually
unquestioned at the time. However, the empirical arguments against this view
still seem sound. And added to them, we now have the conceptual economy-based
argument that LF movement is just of features.
There is, I believe, a natural way to resolve the evident contradiction.
Koizumi (1993, 1995), revising and extending ideas of Johnson (1991), argues
that accusative Case is checked overtly in English, just like nominative Case.[6] The
accusative NP overtly raises to Spec of AgrO (with V raising to a
still higher head position, the V head of a 'shell' VP). If this is correct, the
seemingly paradoxical asymmetry is immediately reduced to the independent
pied-piping asymmetry in Chomsky's theory of movement. In the there
construction, the only movement is the covert movement of the formal features of
the associate to the Agr head. For an ECM subject or the object of a transitive
or unaccusative, the movement is overt, hence, of the entire NP. Under this
circumstance, all of the semantic/referential properties necessary for licensing
anaphors, NPIs, and bound pronouns are raised. Plausibly, when only features
move, these properties are left behind, along with the quantificational/scope
properties that Chomsky already argued are left behind.
Earlier, I mentioned that Chomsky (1995), contrary to what is argued here,
claims that raised formal features do license anaphors. His claim is based on
two phenomena. The first is the Lasnik and Saito paradigms that I have discussed
in some detail. Those paradigms provide strong evidence that there is relevant
raising. But to resolve the apparent contradiction with the inability of the
associate of there in existential constructions to display high behavior,
I have suggested, following Koizumi, that raising to accusative Case position is
actually overt.[7] Since overt raising is of the entire constituent, these facts
(and the corresponding facts with simple transitives) provide no evidence for
binding potential of mere features.
Chomsky's second argument involves control. He presents an example suggesting
that the associate of there behaves as if it is high in its ability to
control PRO in an adjunct:
(60) There arrived three men (last night) without [PRO
identifying
As (61) shows, a typical object cannot control PRO in this construction:
(61) *I met three men (last night) without identifying themselves
Thus, Chomsky reasons that feature raising, in this instance to
AgrS, does create new control configurations, and, a fortiori,
new binding configurations. Momentarily, I will question the generality of the
control phenomenon, but even if Chomsky turns out to be correct about control,
it might not be necessary to draw a broader conclusion about binding. There are
significant semantic and syntactic differences between binding and control. This
issue would take us too far afield here, but see Lasnik (1992a) for some
discussion.
At this point, I would like to examine a bit further the interesting control
phenomenon brought up by Chomsky. Chomsky implies that the associate of there in
(60) is behaving just as an overtly raised subject, as in (62), would.
(62) Three men arrived (last night) without PRO identifying themselves
But already there is some difference. While (62) is perfect, (60) is somewhat
degraded for many speakers. This contrast is heightened if the adverbial is
fronted:
(63) Without PRO identifying themselves, three men arrived
(64) ?*Without identifying themselves, there arrived three men
Further, under raising, the contrast between structures like (60) and (62)
greatly intensifies. In the following examples, the adverbial is intended as
being in the higher clause, along with the raised subject or there:
(65) Someone seems to be available without PRO seeming to be
eager (66) *There seems to be someone available without PRO
seeming
It is not obvious why this should be so if raised features of the associate
of there can control. Finally, other examples structurally identical to the
original (60) are considerably less acceptable, as seen in (67).
(67) ?*There arrived three men (last night) without PRO saying hello
Given all of these facts, though I agree with Chomsky that (60) is reasonably
good, I suggest that we should at least consider the possibility that that
example is not representative, and that even for purposes of control, feature
raising doesn't suffice.
One problem would still remain with respect to the control constructions
though. Consider once again Uriagereka's example, repeated here:
(68) There arrived two knights on each other's horses
I have rejected expletive replacement as the explanation for the binding
here. Further, I have rejected feature raising as the correct account, for
reasons discussed at length above. That seems to leave no account at all. But
recall now Lasnik and Saito's observation that even objects of standard
transitives have similar binding potential:
(69) I saw two men on each other's birthdays
The account I have presented for the latter fact involves overt raising of
the complement of the verb to Spec of AgrO. Elsewhere (Lasnik 1992b,
1995c) I have argued, following Belletti (1988), that unaccusative verbs do
license a Case on their complements (though not accusative Case). Belletti gave
a strong argument that the Case in question is inherent rather than structural.
Now it is generally assumed that inherent Case is licensed in the head
complement configuration, hence does not involve any raising. However,
Lasnik(1995c) questions that assumption, arguing that all Case, whether
structural or inherent, is licensed in the same Spec configuration. There, I
assumed that the movement to that position is covert, but given the perspective
of the present paper, it might well be overt. Below, I will have more to say
about the claim that inherent Case is structurally parallel to structural Case,
but for the moment, note that if it is correct, (68) can potentially receive
exactly the same treatment as (69), with two knights raising overtly to
Spec of AgrO, where it can bind the anaphor, and arrive
raising still higher. Chomsky's example (62) could be nicely accomodated in just
this way. Further, the ungrammaticality of (66) is still predicted: the
associate of there remains in the lower clause. But (61) is mysterious,
as is (67). The first of these two examples plausibly receives a non-structural
account, as control is known to involve (in addition to structure) thematic
properties.The second, though, I will have to leave for future research.
Evidence that inherent Case is 'structural' is presented by Stjepanovi
(1996). Following Lasnik(1995c), Stjepanovic pursues 'symmetry' in the Case
system, the idea that all Case is licensed in the same structural configuration.
Recall that early minimalist arguments against 'government' had the same basic
motivation.[8] Stjepanovi explores inherent Case in Serbo-Croatian (SC) in
detail, and presents compelling evidence that inherently Case marked NPs are
just as high as structurally Case marked NPs. Stjepanovi first observes that SC
has many verbs with the lexical property of licensing Case other than accusative
(hence presumably inherent) on their complements. For example, 'vladati' (rule)
and 'ovladati' (master) license instrumental, 'pomo i' (help) licenses dative,
and 'sjetiti' (remember) licenses genitive. With this much as background,
consider first the binding behavior of accusative object:
(70) Slikao je Samprasa i Ivanisevic a za vrijeme
me 'He photographed Sampras and Ivanisevic
(Acc.) during
As in English, the accusative object can bind into the adverbial. Now observe
that a dative object has the same binding potential:[9]
(71) Pomogao je Samprasu i Ivanisevicu u za
vrijeme 'He helped Sampras and Ivanisevic (Dat.)
during
Similarly, Stjepanovic shows that a dative quantifier, just like an
accusative quantifier, can successfully bind a pronoun within an adverbial, thus
obviating WCO:
(72) Ona kritikuje svakogi bez njegovogi
znanja (73) Ona pomogne svakomi bez njegovogi
znanja
Stjepanovic concludes from a range of facts like these that both structurally
and inherently Case marked NPs raise to Spec of AgrO.[10] She
does not commit herself on whether the movement is overt or covert, but given
the discussion above, I conclude that it is overt.
Given the conceptual argument for symmetry in the Case licensing system, and
the facts from SC in support of it, there is reason to doubt a conjecture of
mine in Lasnik (1993). There, I suggested that reflexives are licensed via
movement to Agr, to be in a Spec-Head relation with their antecedents in Spec of
Agr. I further conjectured that in languages where reflexives are strictly
subject oriented, non-nominative Cases are all inherent, and therefore licensed
in situ. S.-W.Kim (1994) has a somewhat similar proposal. Kim shows that the
height effects seen in English ECM constructions do not arise with Korean ECM
and concludes that the ECM subject does not raise to Spec of AgrO (in
fact, that there is no AgrO in Korean). He gives several paradigms,
one of them centering on caki, one of the Korean reflexives. The crucial
ECM example is reproduced in (74).
(74) *Ku kemsa-nun [Chelswui-lul ywucoy-lako]
cakii-uycaypan-eyse
However, J.-S. Kim (1996) offers another interpretation of the facts. J.-S.
Kim suggests that Korean differs from English not in how Case is licensed, but
rather in when it is. In English, raising to the Case position is overt (driven
by a strong feature). If the relevant feature is weak in Korean, then the
movement will be covert, and hence just of formal features. As seen above, new
binding configurations would then not be created.
This would be a good place to end this discussion, except that conscience
forces me to acknowledge a puzzling array of facts in Japanese, presented by
Yatsushiro (1996). So far, with the possible exception of one rather unclear
control example, (67), an overwhelmingly consistent pattern has emerged: scope
and binding go together, and both are 'low' except when there is overt raising.
The analysis, slightly modifying Chomsky (1995), is that covert raising affects
only formal features, but that scope (Chomsky's proposal) and binding (my
extension) involve more than formal features. The mysterious fact about Japanese
is that scope and binding apparently diverge, and in just the way that Chomsky
claims (evidently incorrectly) that they do in English. Yatsushiro provides
strong arguments that in Japanese unaccusative constructions, the complement of
the unaccusative verb invariably remains in its underlying position at
S-structure. It is then not surprising that the complement has 'low' scope (even
if it raises in LF, since that raising would be just of formal features).
According to Yatsushiro, in (75) daremo-ga ('everyone') necessarily takes
narrow scope with respect to dokoka-ni ('somewhere').
(75) Dokoka-ni daremo-ga ita
somewhere>everyone What is not at all expected is that the complement can bind into the
locative, but that is just what happens:
(76) [Otagai-no heya|-ni [Uli to Susi]-ga
ita
Yatsushiro concludes, plausibly enough, that the features of the NP
complement covertly raise, and they license the anaphor from that raised
position, but do not create high scope. To distinguish Japanese from English,
she observes that in the relevant English constructions, the 'Extended
Projection Principle', which demands that a clause have a subject, has been
satisfied in overt syntax (by there). She further suggests that subject
position is completely unfilled overtly in the corresponding Japanese
constructions, the 'EPP feature' being weak. The covert raising in English would
then be just of agreement features, while in Japanese it would be of these plus
the EPP feature. Either the combination, or the EPP feature alone, would then
provide the crucial ability to license the anaphor. This is a potentially
promising compromise between Chomsky's account and the one advocated above. The
question of whether it can handle the full range of phenomena awaits further
research.
which book that Johni likes
b.
There are/*is men here
Based on the acceptability of (15), Uriagereka
proposes that anaphors need not be licensed at S-structure, reasoning that the
required c-command relation between two knights and each other
holds at LF (16) but not at S-structure (15).[2]
[which book that
Johni likes]
good job offers]
given good job offers]
b. *There seems to
hisi lawyer to have been some
defendanti
at the scene
during each other's
trials
during each other's trials
during hisi trial
of the crime] during
hisi trial
any of the trials
any of the trials
themselves
to get the job
to be eager to get the job
meca jednog protiv drugog
each other's matches'
meca jednog protiv drugog
each other's matches'
'She criticizes everyone (Acc.)
without his knowing'
'She helps everyone (Dat.)
without his knowing'
cungmyengha-ass-ta
'The prosecutor
demonstrated [Chelswu (Acc.) to be
guilty]
in his (reflexive) trial'
somewhere-Loc everyone-Nom be-past
'Everyone was somewhere'
*everyone>somewhere
each other-gen rooms-Loc Uli and
Susi-Nom be-past
'Uli and Susi were in
each other's rooms'
*This research was supported in part by NSF Grant SBR-951088. I would like to acknowledge the helpful suggestions of Zeljko Boskovi and the invaluable editorial assistance of Arthur Stepanov.
[1]. The Belletti and Rizzi approach, where Condition A can be satisfied anywhere in the course of the derivation, was motivated by an interesting class of putative 'reconstruction' effects, as in (i), alongside the standard examples as in (ii).
(i) Pictures of himself please John
(ii) Pictures of himself seem to John to be ugly
Belletti and Rizzi argue that at an early point in the derivation of (i), parallel to (ii), John bears the appropriate c-command relation to himself. Larson(1988) adopts the Belletti and Rizzi theory, but somewhat paradoxically, it would appear. Larson's major goal is to account for a class of binding asymmetries seen in English double object constructions discussed by Barss and Lasnik (1986). (iii) and (iv) are representative instances.
(iii) I showed the professors each other's students
(iv) *I showed each other's students the professors
Larson argues at great length for an analysis of double object constructions in which the first object begins lower than the second but raises to a position that is higher. The grammaticalitity of (iii) is thus straightforwardly explained on Larson's assumptions. However, as noted by Hoekstra (1991), the account falsely predicts symmetrical, rather than asymmetrical, binding, since licensing of the higher surface reciprocal in (iv) could have obtained in the earlier structure where it was actually lower than its antecedent the professors.
[2]. Actually, according to the specific analysis of expletive-argument pairs in Chomsky (1986), (15) would straight-forwardly satisfy the binding requirement of the anaphor at S-structure, since Chomsky claimed that throughout the derivation expletives are coindexed with their associated arguments. But see Lasnik (1992) for arguments against this position.
[3]. I don't give a minimal pair here, such as "I saw two knights on each other's horses" because of the possibility of taking the material after the verb as an NP, "two knights on each other's horses". No such possibility exists for the example in the text.
[4]. I will return to an alternative structural possibility presented by Larson (1988).
[5]. See Chomsky (1986) for arguments against raising to object position and Lasnik and Saito (1991) for discussion of those arguments.
[6]. See Lasnik (1995a,b) for further arguments.
[7]. See Lasnik (1995b) for further arguments based on an ellipsis process.
[8]. See Lasnik (1993) for discussion.
[9]. The particular reciprocal construction in theseexamples is apparently disappearing from the language,so informants report that it has a somewhat archaicflavor. The crucial point for present purposes is thatthe status is the same whether the antecedent is accusative or dative.
[10]. Stjepanovi acknowledges the possibility of aLarsonian alternative, but presents an argument againstit. See Branigan (1992) and Bo[sinvcircumflex]kovi (in press) foradditional arguments.
References
Barss, A. (1986). Chains and anaphoric dependence:On reconstruction and its implications. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Barss, A., and Lasnik, H. (1986). A note on anaphora and double objects. Linguistic Inquiry 17:347-354. [Reprinted in Essays on anaphora, H. Lasnik,1989. 143-148. Dordrecht: Kluwer.]
Belletti, A. (1988). The Case of unaccusatives.Linguistic Inquiry 19:1-34.
Belletti, A., and Rizzi, L. (1988). Psych-verbs and theta theory. Natural Language and LinguisticTheory 6:291-352.
Boskovic, Z . (In press). On certain violations of the Superiority Condition, AgrO and economy of derivation. Journal of Linguistics.
Branigan, P. (1992). Subjects and complementizers. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Chomsky, N. (1973). Conditions on transformations. In A festschrift for Morris Halle, eds. S. Anderson and P. Kiparsky, 232-286. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of Language. New York: Praeger.
Chomsky, N. (1991). Some notes on economy of derivation and representation. In Principles and parameters in comparative grammar, ed. R. Freidin, 417-454.Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
den Dikken, M. (1995). Binding, expletives, and levels. Linguistic Inquiry 26:347-354.
Fiengo, R. (1977). On trace theory. Linguistic Inquiry 8:35-62.
Hoekstra, E. (1991). On double objects in English and Dutch. In Views on phrase structure, eds. K. Leffel, and D. Bouchard, 83-95. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Johnson, K. (1991). Object positions. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 9:577-636.
Kim, J.-S. (1996). On ellipsis and focus movement in Korean and Japanese. Ms. University of Connecticut,Storrs.
Kim, S.-W. (1994). Against AgrOP in Korean. In Explorations in generative grammar, eds. Kim, Y.-S.,Lee, B.-C., Yang, H.-K., and Yoon, J.-Y. 213-232.Seoul: Hankuk Publishing Co.
Koizumi, M. (1993). Object agreement phrases and the split VP hypothesis. In Papers on Case and agreement I: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 18, eds. J.Bobaljik and C. Phillips, 99-148, MIT.
Koizumi, M. (1995). Phrase structure in minimalist syntax. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
Larson, R. (1988). On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19:335-91.
Lasnik, H. (1992a). Two notes on control and binding. In Control and grammar, eds. R. Larson, S.Iatridou, U. Lahiri and J. Higginbotham, 235-252. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Lasnik, H. (1992b). Case and expletives: Notes toward a parametric account. Linguistic Inquiry 23:381-405.
Lasnik, H. (1993). Lectures on minimalist syntax. UConn Working Papers Occasional Papers in Linguistics 1, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Lasnik, H. (1995a). Last resort and Attract F. In Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Meeting of the Formal Linguistics Society of Mid-America, Volume One: Phonology & Syntax I, eds. L. Gabriele, D. Hardison, and R. Westmoreland, 62-81. Indiana University LinguisticsClub.
Lasnik, H. (1995b). A note on Pseudogapping. In Papers on minimalist syntax, MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 27, eds. R. Pensalfini and H. Ura. MIT.
Lasnik, H. (1995c). Case and expletives revisited: On greed and other human failings. Linguistic Inquiry 26: 615-633.
Lasnik, H., and Saito, M. (1991). On the subject of infinitives. In Papers from the 27th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society Part One: The General Session, eds. L. M. Dobrin, L. Nichols, and R.M. Rodriguez, 324-343. Chicago Linguistic Society, University of Chicago, Chicago.
Lasnik, H., and Saito, M. (1992). Move alpha. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Martin, R. (1992). On the distribution and Case features of PRO. Ms., University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Martin, R. (1996). A minimalist theory of PRO and control. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Postal, P. (1974). On raising: One rule of English grammar and its theoretical implications. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Saito, M. (1989). Scrambling as semantically vacuous A'-movement. In Alternative conceptions of phrase structure, eds. M. R. Baltin and A. S. Kroch,182-200. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Stjepanovi , S. (1996). Is inherent Case structural? To appear in Proceedings of FASL 5.
Uriagereka, J. (1988). On government. Doctoral dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs..
Yatsushiro, K. (1996). On the unaccusative construction and nominative Case licensing. Ms. University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Howard Lasnik
University of Connecticut
lasnik@uconnvm.uconn.edu